THE Of SILENG THE LAMBS v 4 = tl How industrial farming harms humans By Adam Tatelman, Staff Writer Per farming: the industrial process that converts carbohydrates to animal protein for mass distribution and consumption. If these terms seem too clinical, that’s because they lack the ethical context, without which the only concern is efficiency. Consequently, we must consider the methods by which such efficiency is achieved as well as the harm industrial agribusiness inflicts on both humanity and animals alike. Since the average North American citizen consumes almost 14 ounces of meat per day, producing 99 per cent of all North American meat products—which factory farms do—is a tall order. According to the North American Meat Institute (NAMI), 8.6 billion chickens, 33.2 million cattle, 239.4 million turkeys, 2.3 million sheep, and 12 million hogs were raised for slaughter by factory farms in 2013. That’s over 93 billion pounds of meat, consistent with the average rate of consumption. This proves that there is generally no surplus; the great efficiency of factory farms is their ability to distribute all of their production every year. Considering the sheer size of this inventory, that’s impressive. How do factory farms achieve this level of efficiency? Logically, the life of a livestock animal from birth to slaughter must be as brief as possible, while still allowing for its maximum growth potential in this time frame. Livestock must also be bred as quickly and in as great a quantity as is manageable, ensuring high population at all times. Expenses on feed and care must be minimized, and any unfit animals must be discarded. Factory farms continent- wide have a booming clientele in the form of chain stores s- and fast-food distributors like McDonalds, Tim Hortons, Saputo, and many others. They are both the primary distributors and beneficiaries of animal meat products; they are also listed as partners of the National Farm Animal Care Council (NFACC) which regulates Canadian factory farming practices, primarily to promote the factory farm business model. The vested interest here is obvious, so what kind of farming methods does the NFACC permit? Consider the life of an average factory-farmed egg-laying chicken. She spends her short life packed inside a wire cage with up to 10 other chickens where each bird is allotted less than 8.5 by u inches of space. Many go stir crazy from the crowding and peck each other to death. To avoid this, their beaks are clipped off—no anesthetic is provided, since that is an unnecessary expense. Through weeks of malnutrition, these chickens are kept in a perpetual egg-laying state. After a couple of years, a hen’s productivity slows. No longer useful, she is slaughtered. Broiler chickens live similar lives, except they are bred for maximum breast size—most cannot even stand due to their weight. Ducks and geese are force fed through tubes for weeks at a time in order to swell their livers to many times their normal size, in order to make foie gras. Sows spend six months in tiny crates, forced to breed again and again, repeatedly traumatized as each litter is taken away from them. Beef cattle spend a year confined in barren feedlots, crowded shoulder-to-shoulder and knee-deep in their own waste, force-fed improper grain diets which are engineered solely to promote rapid weight gain. Like sows, dairy cows spend their entire lives in a traumatic cycle of pregnancy in order to stimulate perpetual lactation. The newborns are treated most harshly. Male offspring of dairy cows live six weeks in tiny crates, fattened for veal in enclosures that keep them from even turning around. Since there is no market for male offspring of egg-laying hens, they are euthanized moments after they hatch. Piglets are castrated at birth without anesthetic. All of this is done in the name of efficiency; it seems ethics and efficiency in factory farming co-exist only up to the vanishing point where greed meets opportunity. This method of farming is predicated upon the idea that animals exist to be used by humans; that they have no rights, cannot have rights, and that there is no ethical problem with treating them like farm equipment instead of sentient creatures that require humane care. This dichotomy breeds considerable academic debate on the “personhood” of farm animals. Theoretically interesting, but often the focus shifts from advocating for ethical restrictions on industrial agribusiness to debating whether those restrictions are needed. Abolitionists like Tom Regan, an animal rights advocate, claim that all forms of life have equal and inherent value, and thus a right to basic humane treatment. Their opponents, like University of Michigan philosophy professor Carl Cohen, maintain that animals, lacking the ability to make or enforce moral claims, cannot have rights or obligations of any kind. Total abolition of animal